Judgments

Decision Information

Decision Content

A-225-91
Her Majesty the Queen (Appellant) (Defendant)
v.
Walter Stanley Belczowski (Respondent) (Plaintiff)
INDEXED AS: BELCZOWSEI Y. CANADA (C.A.)
Court of Appeal, Pratte, Hugessen and Desjardins JJ.A.—Edmonton, January 28; Ottawa, February 17, 1992.
Constitutional law — Charter of Rights — Democratic rights — Convicts denied right to vote by Canada Elections Act, s. 51(e) — Whether disqualification justified by Charter, s. I — Application of test in R. v. Oakes — Test modified by sub sequent case law — Test not misapplied by Trial Judge herein
— Charter, s. 3 right to vote clearly worded, not requiring judicial interpretation — Right to vote going to legitimacy of free and democratic society, more in need of constitutional pmtection than other guaranteed rights — Legislative purpose of s. 51(e) considered — None apparent upon textual analysis
— Crown arguing s. 51(e) having 3 objectives: (1) maintain sanctity of franchise; (2) preserve integrity of voting process; (3) sanction offenders — Alleged objectives symbolic, abstract
— While legislation may legitimately have symbolic objective, Oakes test whether `pressing and substantial" — Doubtful symbolic objective can justify abrogation of constitutional rights — S. 51(e) not having objectives claimed for it — Arbi trary, unfair, based on irrational considerations — Over- and under-inclusiveness of provision — Failing proportionality test.
Elections — Canada Elections Act, s. 51(e) providing penal institution inmates shall not vote at an election — Legislation held to infringe Charter, s. 3 in Gould — Whether disqualifica tion justified by Charter, s. 1 — Right to vote going to founda tion, legitimacy of democratic society — More in need of con stitutional protection than other guaranteed rights — S. 51(e) bearing no logical relationship to objectives of other paragraphs — No legislative purpose apparent from textual analysis — Objective of preserving integrity of voting process unrelated to practicalities of convicts voting — Even Crown unclear as to s. 51(e)'s true objective — Legislation too broad, narrow to ensure decent, responsible citizenry — Holdover from time when thought, for security, administrative reasons, impossible convicts should vote — Right taken away in irra tional pattern: those incarcerated on enumeration or voting day regardless of sentence.
Penitentiaries — Canada Elections Act, s. 51(e) disqualify ing every penal institution inmate from voting at election — Infringing Charter, s. 3 right to vote — Whether justified by Charter, s. 1 — Question as to true objective of s. 51(e) — Objective of preserving integrity of voting process unrelated to practicalities of convicts voting: Crown not invoking adminis trative, security problems in justification of s. 51(e) — Depriv ing convicts of vote not ringing declaration of principle but invisible infringement of group's rights — As to objective of punishment, legislation unrelated to nature of conduct pun ished — Legislation historic holdover from time when thought impossible, for security reasons, convicts should vote — True objective to satisfy widely held stereotype of convicts as no- good, sub-human life form to be denied all rights.
This was an appeal from a judgment of Strayer J. who granted declaratory relief and held that paragraph 51(e) of the Canada Elections Act was contrary to section 3 of the Cana- dian Charter of Rights and Freedoms. This conflict of legisla tion has been, in any event, settled by the Federal Court of Appeal in Attorney General of Canada v. Gould which ruled that paragraph 51(e) cannot stand unless, by virtue of section 1 of the Charter, it is found to be a reasonable limit demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. An appeal to the Supreme Court of Canada was eventually dismissed. There fore, the only issue for consideration by the Court was whether the disqualification of prisoners from the right to vote was jus tified by section 1 of the Charter.
Held, the appeal should be dismissed.
The classic statement of the criteria which must be satisfied for a limit to be reasonable and demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society is that of the Supreme Court of Canada in R. v. Oakes. The test, which looks both to the means and to the ends of the infringing legislation, has been refined and slightly modified in two significant aspects. First, the require ment of a "pressing and substantial" objective for the legisla tion now applies less strictly to some categories of cases. Sec ond, the proportionality test will itself vary somewhat, depending on the nature of the legislation and the kind of bal ancing of interests which Parliament had to do in enacting it. Since the right to vote in Charter, section 3 is cast in straight forward and unambiguous terms requiring no judicial interpre tation, the Courts should have no difficulty in measuring legis lation against them with a high degree of certainty. The requirement of a "pressing and substantial" objective is the appropriate measure to be used in examining the purpose of paragraph 51(e).
The first step in applying the Oakes test to the impugned legislation is to ascertain if its objectives are of "sufficient importance to warrant overriding a constitutionally protected right or freedom". The right to vote, which goes to the very foundations and legitimacy of a free and democratic society, needs even more constitutional protection than most of the other guaranteed rights and freedoms. It is so firmly entrenched in our Constitution that, unlike other protected rights and freedoms, it is excluded from the override power afforded to Parliament and the legislatures by subsection 33(1) of the Charter. Section 51 of the Canada Elections Act, when read as a whole, seems to have a variety of disparate purposes. Paragraph (e) stands by itself, bearing no logical relationship to the objectives underlying the other paragraphs of the section. One cannot, upon a textual analysis of the section, assign any legislative purpose to paragraph 51(e). The three objectives invoked by the appellant, namely to affirm and maintain the sanctity of the franchise, to preserve the integrity of the voting process and to sanction offenders, are all symbolic and abstract. For example, the objective of preserving the integrity of the voting process has nothing to do with the practicalities of permitting prisoners to vote: the appellant conceded that administrative and security problems could not be invoked to justify paragraph 51(e). While legislation may legitimately have a purely symbolic objective, the question on the first branch of the Oakes test is not the legitimacy of the legislative purpose but its importance, that is to say whether it is "press- ing and substantial". It is very doubtful whether a wholly sym bolic objective can ever be sufficiently important to justify the abrogation of rights which are themselves so important and fundamental as to have been enshrined in our Constitution. The purely symbolic objective could not be characterized as pressing or substantial. Depriving convicts of the vote was not a ringing and unambiguous public declaration of principle but an almost invisible infringement of the rights of a group of persons. The operation of the legislation did nothing to support the view that its objectives were what the Crown alleges them to be. If the purpose was to ensure a decent and responsible citizenry, the legislation was both too broad and narrow. It is too broad in that the exclusion catches all kinds of offender: the person imprisoned for inability to pay a fine as well as the murderer. It is too narrow in that it fails to catch those who, from illness or incapacity, are institutionalized and unable to participate fully in the democratic process, and it also over looks those who, through disinterest or distraction, do not so participate. With regard to the alleged objective of punishment, the legislation bears no discernible relationship to the quality or nature of the conduct being punished. The objectives advanced by the Crown in support of paragraph 51(e) are unacceptable; the latter represents nothing more than an his toric holdover from the time when it was thought, for practical, security and administrative reasons, that it was simply impossi ble for convicts to vote. That ground has been abandoned by the Crown and would in any event be unsustainable under modern conditions. The true objective of paragraph 51(e) may have been to satisfy the widely held stereotype of the prison inmate as a no-good almost sub-human form of life to which
all rights should be indiscriminately denied. That was not an objective which would satisfy section 1 of the Charter.
The second branch of the Oakes test requires a three-stage examination of the means adopted by Parliament to attain the alleged ends. The impugned legislation fails at every stage. First, paragraph 51(e) is not rationally connected to the alleged objectives. The fact of being in prison is not, by any means, a sure or rational indication that the prisoner is not a decent or responsible citizen: fine defaulters and prisoners of conscience cannot be described as ipso . facto indecent and irresponsible. Imprisonment bears no necessary connection to inability to participate fully in the democratic process and is not a safe or rational indicator that the prisoner should be further punished by being deprived of the right to vote as a consequence of his conduct. On the other hand, the legislation fails to exclude all manner of persons who are clearly not decent and responsible citizens, who are unwilling or unable to participate in the pro cess, or whose conduct merits their being deprived of the franchise. It is not the imperfection of the application of para graph 51(e) which is being here invoked but the imperfection of the text itself. Failing in all its alleged objectives, paragraph 51(e) is arbitrary, unfair and based on irrational considerations. Nor was the second branch of this part of the test, the require ment that the legislative measure impair the guaranteed right as little as possible, met. Not only was the right taken away alto gether but, because of the very nature of the right to vote itself, it was taken away in an irregular and irrational pattern. Finally, paragraph 51(e) could not meet the third branch of the test which requires an examination of the proportionality between the effect of the legislation and its objectives. For reasons already suggested and even assuming the alleged objectives to be valid, paragraph 51(e) could not be characterized as a mea sured and proportionate means of achieving them with due regard for the importance of the rights taken away.
STATUTES AND REGULATIONS JUDICIALLY CONSIDERED
Canada Elections Act, R.S.C. 1970 (1st Supp.), c. 14, s. 14(4)(e).
Canada Elections Act, R.S.C., 1985, c. E-2, s. 51.
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, being Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, Schedule B, Canada Act 1982, 1982, c. 11 (U.K.) [R.S.C., 1985, Appendix II, No. 44], ss. 1, 3, 15.
Constitutional Act, 1791, 31 Geo. III, c. 31 (U.K.) [R.S.C., 1985, Appendix II, No. 3], s. XXIII.
Criminal Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46.
CASES JUDICIALLY CONSIDERED
FOLLOWED:
Gould v. Attorney General of Canada et al., [1984] 2 S.C.R. 124; (1984), 13 D.L.R. (4th) 485; 42 C.R. (3d) 88; 53 N.R. 394; R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; (1986), 26 D.L.R. (4th) 200; 24 C.C.C. (3d) 321; 50 C.R. (3d) 1; 19 C.R.R. 308; 65 N.R. 87; 14 O.A.C. 335; Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143; (1989), 56 D.L.R. (4th) 1; [1989] 2 W.W.R. 289; 34 B.C.L.R. (2d) 273; 36 C.R.R. 193; 91 N.R. 255; McKinney v. Uni versity of Guelph, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 229; (1990), 76 D.L.R. (4th) 545; 91 CLLC 17,004; Stoffman v. Vancouver Gen eral Hospital, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 483; [1991] 1 W.W.R. 577; (1990), 52 B.C.L.R. (2d) 1; 91 CLLC 17,003.
APPLIED:
Attorney General of Canada v. Gould, [1984] 1 F.C. 1133; (1984), 13 D.L.R. (4th) 485; 42 C.R. (3d) 88; 54 N.R. 232 (C.A.); Re Hoogbruin et al. and Attorney-Gen eral of British Columbia et al. (1985), 24 D.L.R. (4th) 718; [1986] 2 W.W.R. 700; 70 B.C.L.R. 1 (C.A.); Grondin v. Ontario (Attorney General) (1988), 65 O.R. (2d) 427 (H.C.).
CONSIDERED:
Sauvé v. Canada (Attorney General) (1988), 66 O.R. (2d) 234; 53 D.L.R. (4th) 595 (H.C.).
REFERRED TO:
R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd. et al., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295; (1985), 60 A.R. 161; 18 D.L.R. (4th) 321; [1985] 3 W.W.R. 481; 37 Alta. L.R. (2d) 97; 18 C.C.C. (3d) 385; 85 CLLC 14,023; 13 C.R.R. 64; 58 N.R. 81; Jolivet and Barker and The Queen and Solicitor-General of Canada (1983), 1 D.L.R. (4th) 604; 48 B.C.L.R. 121; 7 C.C.C. (3d) 431; 8 C.R.R. 5 (B.C.S.C.); Lévesque v. Canada (Attorney General), [1986] 2 F.C. 287; (1985), 25 D.L.R. (4th) 184 (T.D.); Gould v. Attorney General of Canada, [1984] 1 F.C. 1119; (1984), 42 C.R. (3d) 78 (T.D.).
APPEAL from a judgment of the Trial Division, [1991] 3 F.C. 151; (1991), 5 C.R. (4th) 218; 42 F.T.R. 98 granting declaratory relief and holding that paragraph 51(e) of the Canada Elections Act was
contrary to section 3 of the Charter. Appeal dis missed.
COUNSEL:
Terrence Joyce, Q.C., and Meg Kinnear for
appellant (defendant).
Richard A. Stroppel for respondent (plaintiff).
SOLICITORS:
Deputy Attorney General of Canada for appel lant (defendant).
Brimacombe, Sanderman, Stroppel & Finlayson, Edmonton, for respondent (plaintiff).
The following are the reasons for judgment ren dered in English by
HUGESSEN J.A.: This is an appeal from a judgment of Strayer J. in the Trial Division [[1991] 3 F.C. 151] wherein he granted declaratory relief and held that the provisions of the Canada Elections Act' disquali fying prison inmates from voting were contrary to the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms [being Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, Schedule B, Canada Act 1982, 1982, c. 11 (U.K.) [R.S.C., 1985, Appendix II, No. 44]].
There were several issues before Strayer J. The respondent based his claim on both section 3 and sec tion 15 of the Charter. The appellant denied that either of those sections was breached by the legisla tion and further pleaded that any infringement of Charter guaranteed rights was justified by section 1. The appellant also raised an issue in the Trial Divi sion as to the nature of the relief sought.
In appeal, the issues have been greatly narrowed. Strayer J. did not accept the respondent's arguments based on section 15 and that part of the claim was not pursued before us. The Crown, for its part, aban doned in appeal its arguments as to the appropriate ness of the remedy. In addition, while the Crown urged that the legislation did not run afoul of section
3 of the Charter, we did not call upon the respondent to answer on this point. There remains, thus, only the question of section 1 justification.
At the time the proceedings were commenced in the Trial Division, the relevant disqualification was found in paragraph 14(4)(e) of the Canada Elections Act. 2 By the time the case came to trial, the Revised Statutes of Canada, 1985, had come into effect and
1 R.S.C., 1985, c. E-2.
2 R.S.C. 1970 (1st Supp.), c. 14.
the relevant exclusion, in identical terms, is now found in paragraph 51(e) of the Canada Elections Act. 3 Throughout his reasons and in the formal judg ment, Strayer J. referred to the legislation in its cur rent form, and it is convenient to do likewise here.
Section 51 of the Canada Elections Act reads as follows:
51. The following persons are not qualified to vote at an election and shall not vote at an election:
(a) the Chief Electoral Officer;
(b) the Assistant Chief Electoral Officer;
(c) the returning officer for each electoral district during his term of office, except when there is an equality of votes on a recount, as provided in the Act;
(d) every judge appointed by the Governor in Council other than a citizenship judge appointed under the Citizenship Act;
(e) every person undergoing punishment as an inmate in any penal institution for the commission of any offence;
(h every person who is restrained of his liberty of movement or deprived of the management of his property by reason of mental disease; and
(g) every person who is disqualified from voting under any law relating to the disqualification of electors for corrupt or illegal practices. [Emphasis added.]
Sections 1 and 3 of the Charter read as follows:
1. The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms guaran tees the rights and freedoms set out in it subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society.
3. Every citizen of Canada has the right to vote in an elec tion of members of the House of Commons or of a legislative assembly and to be qualified for membership therein.
As I indicated earlier we did not find it necessary to call on the respondent on the question as to whether or not paragraph 51(e) of the Canada Elec tions Act is in conflict with section 3 of the Charter. Not only are Strayer J.'s reasons on this point above reproach but the question is, in any event, foreclosed in this Court by our decision in Attorney General of Canada v. Gould. 4 In that case, Mahoney J.A., speak ing for the majority of this Court, said at page 1139:
3 Supra, note 1.
4 [1984] 1 F.C. 1133 (C.A.).
Paragraph 14(4)(e) [51(e)] plainly cannot stand unless, by vir tue of section 1 of the Charter, it is found to be a reasonable limit demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. That is the serious issue to be tried. That is what the trial will be all about. [Emphasis added.]
An appeal to the Supreme Court of Canada 5 was dismissed in these terms:
We grant leave to appeal the decision of the Federal Court of Appeal rendered August 31, 1984.
In our view, however, this appeal fails. We generally share the views expressed by Mr. Justice Mahoney speaking for the majority of the Federal Court of Appeal. The appeal is accord ingly dismissed.
This brings us to the question of whether or not the disqualification of prisoners from the right to vote is justified by section 1. The principles are well known and have been many times stated. The test is a two- stage one and looks both to the means and to the ends of the infringing legislation. The classic statement is in R. v. Oakes: 6
To establish that a limit is reasonable and demonstrably jus tified in a free and democratic society, two central criteria must be satisfied. First, the objective, which the measures responsi ble for a limit on a Charter right or freedom are designed to serve, must be "of sufficient importance to warrant overriding a constitutionally protected right or freedom": R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., supra, at p. 352. The standard must be high in order to ensure that objectives which are trivial or discordant with the principles integral to a free and democratic society do not gain s. 1 protection. It is necessary, at a minimum, that an objective relate to concerns which are pressing and substantial in a free and democratic society before it can be characterized as sufficiently important.
s Gould v. Attorney General of Canada et al., [1984] 2 S.C.R. 124, Dickson C.J. The Gould case is too often over looked by those who like to criticize our judicial system for its inability to react quickly when necessary. The matter was heard in the Trial Division on Tuesday and Wednesday, August 28 and 29, 1984, with judgment rendered the latter day. The appeal to this Court was heard on Thursday, August 30, 1984, and judgment rendered the following day. On the next follo wing judicial day, September 4, 1984, (Monday, September 3, 1984, being the Labour Day holiday) the application for leave to appeal and the appeal itself were heard and disposed of in the Supreme Court of Canada.
6 [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, at pp. 138, 139 and 140, Dickson C.J.
Second, once a sufficiently significant objective is recog nized, then the party invoking s. 1 must show that the means chosen are reasonable and demonstrably justified. This involves "a form of proportionality test": R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., supra, at p. 352. Although the nature of the propor tionality test will vary depending on the circumstances, in each case courts will be required to balance the interests of society with those of individuals and groups. There are, in my view, three important components of a proportionality test. First, the measures adopted must be carefully designed to achieve the objective in question. They must not be arbitrary, unfair or based on irrational considerations. In short, they must be rationally connected to the objective. Second, the means, even if rationally connected to the objective in this first sense, should impair "as little as possible" the right or freedom in question: R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., supra, at p. 352. Third, there must be a proportionality between the effects of the mea sures which are responsible for limiting the Charter right or freedom, and the objective which has been identified as of "sufficient importance".
With respect to the third component, it is clear that the gen eral effect of any measure impugned under s. I will be the infringement of a right or freedom guaranteed by the Charter; this is the reason why resort to s. 1 is necessary. The inquiry into effects must, however, go further. A wide range of rights and freedoms are guaranteed by the Charter, and an almost infinite number of factual situations may arise in respect of these. Some limits on rights and freedoms protected by the Charter will be more serious than others in terms of the nature of the right or freedom violated, the extent of the violation, and the degree to which the measures which impose the limit trench upon the integral principles of a free and democratic society. Even if an objective is of sufficient importance, and the first two elements of the proportionality test are satisfied, it is still possible that, because of the severity of the deleterious effects of a measure on individuals or groups, the measure will not be justified by the purposes it is intended to serve. The more severe the deleterious effects of a measure, the more important the objective must be if the measure is to be reasona ble and demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society.
The Oakes test has been refined and slightly modi fied with the passage of time in two significant respects. In the first place, it appears now that the requirement of the "pressing and substantial" objec tive for the legislation has been slackened somewhat for some categories of cases. The comments of Mcln-
tyre J. in Andrews v. Law Society of British Colum- bia, 7 although dissenting on the question of section 1 justification, seem to have found favour:
In Oakes, it was held that to override a Charter guaranteed right the objective must relate to concerns which are "pressing and substantial" in a free and democratic society. However, given the broad ambit of legislation which must be enacted to cover various aspects of the civil law dealing largely with administrative and regulatory matters and the necessity for the Legislature to make many distinctions between individuals and groups for such purposes, the standard of "pressing and sub stantial" may be too stringent for application in all cases. To hold otherwise would frequently deny the community-at-large the benefits associated with sound social and economic legisla tion. In my opinion, in approaching a case such as the one before us, the first question the Court should ask must relate to the nature and the purpose of the enactment, with a view to deciding whether the limitation represents a legitimate exercise of the legislative power for the attainment of a desirable social objective which would warrant overriding constitutionally pro tected rights. [Emphasis added.]
Second, there has been a recognition that the pro portionality test will itself vary somewhat, depending on the nature of the legislation and the kind of bal ancing of interests which Parliament itself may have been called upon to do in enacting it:
The approach to be followed in weighing whether a law constitutes a reasonable limit to a Charter right has been stated on many occasions beginning with R. v. Oakes, supra, and I need merely summarize it here. The onus of justifying a limita tion to a Charter right rests on the parties seeking to uphold the limitation. The starting point of the inquiry is an assessment of the objectives of the law to determine whether they are suffi ciently important to warrant the limitation of the constitutional right. The challenged law is then subjected to a proportionality test in which the objective of the impugned law is balanced against the nature of the right, the extent of its infringement and the degree to which the limitation furthers other rights or policies of importance in a free and democratic society.
This balancing task, as the Court recently stated in United States of America v. Cotroni, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1469, at pp. 1489-90, should not be approached in a mechanistic fashion. For, as was there said, "While the rights guaranteed by the Charter must be given priority in the equation, the underlying values must be sensitively weighed in a particular context against other values of a free and democratic society sought to be promoted by the legislature." Indeed, early in the develop ment of the balancing test, Dickson C.J. underlined that "Both in articulating the standard of proof and in describing the crite ria comprising the proportionality requirement the Court has
7 [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143, at p. 184.
been careful to avoid rigid and inflexible standards"; see R. v. Edwards Books and Art Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713, at pp. 768- 69. Speaking specifically on s. 15 in Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, at p. 198, I thus ventured to articulate the considerations to be borne in mind:
The degree to which a free and democratic society such as Canada should tolerate differentiation based on personal characteristics cannot be ascertained by an easy calculus. There will rarely, if ever, be a perfect congruence between means and ends, save where legislation has discriminatory purposes. The matter must, as earlier cases have held, involve a test of proportionality. In cases of this kind, the test must be approached in a flexible manner. The analysis should be functional, focussing on the character of the clas sification in question, the constitutional and societal impor tance of the interests adversely affected, the relative impor tance to the individuals affected of the benefit of which they are deprived, and the importance of the state interest.
I should add that by state interest, here I include not only those where the state itself is, in the words of the majority in Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [ 1989] 1 S.C.R 927, at p. 994, "the singular antagonist", typically prosecuting crime, but also where the state interest involves "the reconciliation of claims of competing individuals or groups or the distribution of scarce ... resources". l shall have more to say about this later. ,
(McKinney v. University of Guelph, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 229, at pages 280-281, La Forest J.)
As in McKinney, it is important in considering the issues raised by a case like the present to note that judicial evaluation of the state's interest will differ depending on whether the state is the "singular antagonist" of the person whose rights have been violated, as it usually will be where the violation occurs in the context of the criminal law, or whether it is instead defending legislation or other conduct concerned with "the reconciliation of claims of competing individuals or groups or the distribu tion of scarce government resources". See Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927, at p. 994. In the former situation, the courts will be able to determine whether the impugned law or other government conduct is the "least drastic means" for the achievement of the state interest with a considerable measure of certainty, given their familiar ity with the values and operation of the criminal justice system and the judicial system generally. As this Court has noted in Irwin Toy, however, the same degree of certainty may not be achievable in the latter situation.
(Stoffman v. Vancouver General Hospital, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 483, at pages 521-522, La Forest J.)
The appellant argues that Strayer J. erred and mis applied the test, as laid down in Stoffman and McKin- ney, supra, when he held that the government here was indeed in the position of "singular antagonist" to the respondent. This is how the appellant's argument is stated:
In the case at bar, the State is neither the singular antagonist nor is the context criminal law. Rather, this is a case in which the legislature must balance the competing claims of inmates to vote with the claims of society at large to preserve the sanc tity of the franchise and to sanction offenders for violating the social contract.
(Memorandum of fact and law of the Deputy Attor ney General of Canada, page 23.)
I do not agree.
While it is true that the disqualification of prison ers from the right to vote is not strictly speaking a part of the criminal law, it is, in my view, far more analogous to legislation for dealing with and punish ing criminals than to the kind of social legislation mentioned by La Forest J. in the above quotations. In disputes centered around compulsory retirement (Stoffman and McKinney, supra), or the rights of non- citizens to practice law (Andrews, supra), or even the control of advertising directed to children (Irwin Toy), it is relatively simple to identify competing groups each of which constitutes only a part of the body politic. To say, however, as the appellant does in the above quoted extract, that the legislation, here under review, balances the claims of the respondent with those of "society at large", is surely to say no more than that the state, which represents the latter, has interests directly opposed to those targeted by the impugned legislation. This is surely most nearly com parable to the case where the state, representing soci ety at large, decrees that certain types of conduct are forbidden and prosecutes with a view to punishing those who breach the proscription.
What is more, the right to vote in section 3 of the Charter (and the kindred rights set out in sections 4 and 5) are cast in straightforward and unambiguous terms singularly amenable to judicial interpretation. Indeed, it might be more accurate to state that they require no interpretation at all. The courts should have no difficulty in measuring legislation against them with a high degree of certainty and it is very difficult to see how such legislation could raise any question of reconciliation of competing claims or the distribution of limited resources.
For these reasons I am of opinion that this case is far more closely analogous to Oakes than to Andrews. Accordingly, it is also my view that the requirement of a "pressing and substantial" objective is the appro priate measure to be used in examining the purpose of paragraph 51(e).
I turn now to the application of the Oakes test itself. The first step is to ascertain if the objectives of the impugned legislation are of "sufficient impor tance to warrant overriding a constitutionally pro tected right or freedom". 8 It is significant in this con nection to note the rather special status of the constitutionally protected right which is here in issue. The framers of the Charter recognized that the right to vote, going as it does to the very foundations and legitimacy of a free and democratic society, is, if any thing, even more in need of constitutional protection than most of the other guaranteed rights and free doms, no matter how important the latter may be. The point was well put in the Court of Appeal of British Columbia: 9
By way of preface it is to be noted that the right to vote is a democratic right so strongly entrenched in the Charter that unlike the fundamental freedoms set out in s. 2, and the legal rights set forth in ss. 7 to 15, it is not subject to the override clause afforded the Legislature by s. 33(1). Accordingly, sub ject only to obvious exclusions such as minors or mental incompetents, the right to vote is firmly entrenched in our Constitution.
8 R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd. et al., [1985] I S.C.R. 295, at p. 352, Dickson J.
9 Re Hoogbruinn et al. and Attorney-General of British Columbia et al. (1985), 24 D.L.R. (4th) 718, at p. 720.
It was echoed by the Ontario High Court in Grondin v. Ontario (Attorney General):'°
The right to vote has been guaranteed to every Canadian citi zen by s. 3 of the Charter. If a limitation on such a fundamental aspect of democracy had been contemplated by those who framed our constitution, I am of the view that such a limitation could have been specifically provided for and made infinitely clear. By way of comparison, the exclusion of prisoners from the franchise is specifically sanctioned by the Fourteenth Amendment to the United States Constitution. In contrast, however, the right to vote is so firmly entrenched in the Cana- dian Charter that, unlike other protected rights and freedoms, it is excluded from the override power afforded to parliament and the legislature by s. 33(1) of the Charter.
What then is the objective or legislative purpose of paragraph 51(e)? Certainly it is not immediately apparent and does not leap from the page on a read ing of the section as a matter of first impression. Indeed, section 51, when read as a whole, seems to have a variety of disparate purposes.
For convenience I reproduce paragraphs (a) to (g):
51....
(a) the Chief Electoral Officer;
(b) the Assistant Chief Electoral Officer;
(c) the returning officer for each electoral district during his term of office, except when there is an equality of votes on a recount, as provided in the Act;
(d) every judge appointed by the Governor in Council other than a citizenship judge appointed under the Citizenship Act;
(e) every person undergoing punishment as an inmate in any penal institution for the commission of any offence;
(D every person who is restrained of his liberty of movement or deprived of the management of his property by reason of mental disease; and
(g) every person who is disqualified from voting under any law relating to the disqualification of electors for corrupt or illegal practices.
The objective of the exclusions mentioned in paragraphs (a), (b) and (c) seems obviously to be to guarantee the fairness of the electoral process. To adopt a sporting analogy, the referee, umpire and linesmen are not to take part in the game.
10 (1988), 65 O.R. (2d) 427, at p. 430, Bowlby J.
The objective of the exclusion in paragraph (d) is quite different. It is aimed not at the fairness of elec tions but at the appearance of impartiality and free dom from partisanship of those who are called upon to decide disputes between the state and its citizens.
Paragraph (f), by contrast, seems to have for its purpose a guarantee of an absolute minimum of intel lectual capacity in those who exercise the franchise.
Finally, paragraph (g) is manifestly a punitive pro vision attaching to past conduct related to the electo ral process itself.
What are we to make of paragraph (e) which is located in the middle of this list? It seems to bear no logical relationship to the objectives underlying paragraphs (a), (b) and (c) nor to that underlying par agraph (d). It equally cannot today share a common purpose with paragraph (f), although it may well be the case that historically, and before the advent of proxy and mail votes, it was thought to be simply impossible that anyone deprived of his liberty of movement, for whatever reason, would be physically able to cast a vote. Finally, there may be a superficial resemblance between the objectives of paragraphs (e) and (g) although it should be noted that the latter exclusion is expressly framed in terms of fitting the punishment to the crime in a way that is wholly absent from the former.
In my view, and based solely upon a textual analy sis of the section, one cannot, with confidence, assign any legislative purpose to paragraph 51(e). The appellant, however, asserts, based on the opinion evi dence given at trial by a professor of political sci ence, that the paragraph has three objectives as fol lows:
(a) to affirm and maintain the sanctity of the franchise in our democracy;
(b) to preserve the integrity of the voting process; and
(c) to sanction offenders.
The appellant adopts these objectives and expands on them in the following manner.
The objective of maintaining the sanctity of the franchise is based on the need for a liberal democracy to have a "decent and responsible citizenry" which will voluntarily abide by the laws, or at any rate most
of them. The views of Van Camp J. in Sauvé v. Canada (Attorney General» are quoted with approval:
However, it seems to me that Parliament was justified in limiting the right to vote with the objective that a liberal demo cratic regime requires a decent and responsible citizenry. Such a regime requires that the citizens obey voluntarily; the practi cal efficacy of laws relies on the willing acquiescence of those subject to them. The state has a role in preserving itself by the symbolic exclusion of criminals from the right to vote for the lawmakers. So also, the exclusion of the criminal from the right to vote reinforces the concept of a decent responsible citi zenry essential for a liberal democracy.
The objective of preserving the integrity of the vot ing process has nothing to do with the practicalities of permitting prisoners to vote: the appellant con cedes that administrative and security problems can not be invoked to justify paragraph 51(e).
(Parenthetically, it should be noted here that the appellant has effected a remarkable volte-face on this point. One of the principal grounds of the vigorous defence that was raised in Gould v. Canada, supra, was precisely the security and administrative problems that allegedly would arise if inmate voting were permitted. 12 It also seems to have been relied on in other cases dealing with prisoners' right to vote. 13 That it has now been abandoned lends some credence to the view that the Crown itself does not know what the true objective of paragraph 51(e) really is.)
In any event the Crown's present position is that one of the purposes of disqualifying prisoners is to ensure that only those who can truly participate in the democratic process should be allowed to cast ballots. Prisoners being isolated from society at large, and being temporarily removed from the local communi ties and constituencies of which other voters form part, cannot participate fully in the debate, discussion
11 (1988), 66 O.R. (2d) 234 (H.C.), at p. 238.
12 See the reasons for judgment of the Trial Division, [ 1984] 1 F.C. 1119, at p. 1125.
13 See Jolivet and Barker and The Queen and Solicitor- General of Canada (1983), I D.L.R. (4th) 604 (B.C.S.C.), Taylor J.; Lévesque v. Canada (Attorney General), [1986] 2 F.C. 287 (T.D.), Rouleau J.
and interchange which are essential to the democratic process.
Finally, the objective of sanctioning offenders is said to arise from the state's legitimate interest in punishing those who disobey the law and in expres sing collective disapproval of deliberate actions in breach of the social contract.
In his reasons for judgment, Strayer J. subjected each of these alleged objectives to rigorous and searching analysis. He concluded that objectives (a) and (b) could not realistically be seen as the purpose of paragraph 51(e) and were, in any event, not suffi ciently serious to justify deprivation of a Charter guaranteed right. Objective (c), sanction or punish ment, he found to be more plausible and not invalid in and of itself.
The appellant takes issue with the manner in which Strayer J. approached the first branch of the Oakes test, asserting that it is not proper to isolate each alleged objective and consider them individually one by one. Rather, it is said, a Court should look at the alleged objectives comprehensively and determine whether together and in combination they are suffi ciently serious. Without saying that Strayer J. was wrong, I am quite content to adopt the approach sug gested; I find, however, that in the present case it gives but cold comfort to the Crown.
Viewed together and collectively, the most striking point about the alleged objectives of paragraph 51(e) is that they are all symbolic and abstract. The appel lant admits as much, but maintains that this fact does not prevent them from being legitimate objectives for legislation. With respect, it seems to me that this misses the mark. It is, of course, true that legislation may legitimately have a purely symbolic objective. The question on the first branch of the Oakes test, however, is not the legitimacy of the legislative pur pose but rather its importance, that is to say whether it is "pressing and substantial". For my part, I must say that I have very serious doubts whether a wholly symbolic objective can ever be sufficiently important to justify the taking away of rights which are them selves so important and fundamental as to have been
enshrined in our Constitution. To accept symbolism as a legitimate reason for the denial of Charter rights seems to me to be a course fraught with danger. Even on the lower test of a "desirable social objective" suggested in Andrews, I would have thought that such objective would have to translate into some real intended benefit and not merely some abstract or symbolic notion. To adopt the other course would, it seems to me, expose us to Voltaire's famous jibe that the English had executed Admiral Byng on his own quarterdeck "pour encourager les autres". 14
Assuming, however, for the sake of argument, that a purely symbolic objective may be sufficiently seri ous in some circumstances, it is my view that it can not be so in this case. Depriving prisoners of the vote is not a ringing and unambiguous public declaration of principle. On the contrary it is an almost invisible infringement of the rights of a group of persons who, as long as they remain inside the walls are, to our national disgrace, almost universally unseen and unthought of. If, as I think, therefore, the alleged symbolic objective is one whose symbolism is lost on the great majority of citizens, it is impossible to char acterize that objective as pressing or substantial.
I would also note, in considering the alleged objec tives of paragraph 51(e) collectively, that to conclude that they are indeed the purposes which Parliament had in mind in adopting the legislation requires an act of faith. I have already indicated that there is nothing in the text of the legislation itself to give any clue to its purpose. I would now add that the opera tion of the legislation does nothing to support the view that its objectives are what the Crown alleges them to be. If the purpose is to ensure a decent and responsible citizenry, the legislation is both too broad and narrow. It is too broad in that the exclusion catches not only the crapulous murder but also the fine defaulter who is in prison for no better reason than his inability to pay. The same is true of the alleged objective relating to the integrity of the pro cess: paragraph 51(e) catches those who are serving
14 Candide (1759).
their sentences in an open prison setting where they live in the midst of their communities; it fails to catch those who, from illness or incapacity, are institution alized and unable to participate fully in the demo cratic process. It also, as Strayer J. rightly pointed out, entirely overlooks those who through disinterest or distraction do not so participate. Finally, with regard to the alleged objective of punishment, the legislation bears no discernible relationship to the quality or nature of the conduct being punished. Indeed, on a reading of the text of paragraph 51(e), it
is difficult not to conclude that, if it is imposing pun ishment, such punishment is for imprisonment rather than for the commission of an offence.
In this latter respect, it is interesting to note that paragraph 51(e) differs starkly from its earliest Cana- dian ancestor, being section XXIII of the Constitu tional Act, 1791 [31 Geo. III, c. 31 (U.K.) [R.S.C., 1985, Appendix II, No. 3]]:
XXIII. And be it also enacted by the Authority aforesaid, That no Person shall be capable of voting at any Election of a Member to serve in such Assembly, in either of the said Prov inces, or of being elected at any such Election, who shall have been attainted for Treason or Felony in any Court of Law within any of his Majesty's Dominions, or who shall be within any Description of Persons disqualified by any Act of the Leg islative Council and Assembly of the Province, assented to by his Majesty, his Heirs or Successors.
A denial of the right to vote for persons convicted of treason or felony can readily be understood as a pun ishment for those crimes. A similar denial imposed only on those who are actually in prison looks more like a consequence of that condition than a sanction for the conduct which brought it about in the first place.
Given the foregoing comments, I am not prepared to accept the objectives advanced by the Crown in support of paragraph 51(e). Indeed, it seems to me far more likely, as I have suggested earlier, that the legis lation represents nothing more than an historic holdo ver from the time when it was thought, for practical, security and administrative reasons, that it was quite simply impossible that prisoners should vote. As I have indicated that ground has now been abandoned by the Crown and would in any event be unsustain- able in modern conditions. An examination of Sched-
ule II to the Canada Elections Act, and of its detailed provisions for permitting voting by service person nel, public servants and veterans, in circumstances where it was once thought impossible to conduct a poll, demonstrates the invalidity of such a justifica tion for the exclusion.
Alternatively, and far less commendably, it would appear to me that the true objective of paragraph 51(e) may be to satisfy a widely held stereotype of the prisoner as a no-good almost sub-human form of life to which all rights should be indiscriminately denied. That, it need hardly be said, is not an objec tive which would satisfy section 1 of the Charter.
This brings me to the second branch of the Oakes test which requires a three-stage examination of the means adopted by Parliament to attain the alleged ends. In my view, and for reasons which have already been suggested in the examination of the objectives, this legislation fails at every stage.
First, there is the requirement that paragraph 51(e) be rationally connected to the alleged objectives. It is not. The fact of being in prison is not, by any means, a sure or rational indication that the prisoner is not a decent and responsible citizen. I have already men tioned fine defaulters who shockingly constituted a huge proportion of our prison population. By no means can they be described as ipso facto indecent and irresponsible. It is also not impossible in our society for persons to be in prison for reasons of con science and I doubt that as a society we feel that such persons are not decent and responsible whatever else we might think of them.
By the same token, and for the reasons indicated, imprisonment bears no necessary connection to inability to participate fully in the democratic process and is not, in and of itself, a safe or rational indicator that the prisoner should be further punished by being deprived of his vote as a consequence of the conduct which has led to his being in prison.
On the other side of the coin of rational connection is the fact that the legislation fails to exclude all man ner of persons who are clearly not decent and respon sible citizens, who are unwilling or unable to partici pate in the process, or whose conduct merits their being deprived of the franchise. To this the appellant counters that imperfection of application does not invalidate the law: if many, or even most criminals go uncaught and unpunished, that does not make the Criminal Code [R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46] any less valid. With respect, it appears to me that the argument is specious. It is not the imperfection of the application of paragraph 51(e) which is being here invoked but the imperfection of the text itself. The Criminal Code proscribes and punishes all crimes and criminals even if the police and the courts do not; paragraph 51(e), even if perfectly applied, would still fail dismally in all its alleged objectives. In short, and to recall the words of Oakes, paragraph 51(e) is arbitrary, unfair and based on irrational considerations.
There is little that need to be said of the second branch of this part of the test which requires that the legislative measure impair the guaranteed right as lit tle as possible. I would only note that, not only is the right taken away altogether, but, because of the very nature of the right to vote itself, it is taken away in an irregular and irrational pattern: persons who happen to be in prison on enumeration day, or voting day, no matter how short their sentence, lose the right to vote; others may serve up to four years and three hundred and sixty-four days in prison and never be deprived of the franchise at all.
Finally, the third branch of the test requires an examination of the proportionality between the effect of the legislation and its objectives. For reasons which have already been suggested, paragraph 51(e) cannot meet this test. I have already commented on the over- and under-inclusiveness of the legislation when viewed in the light of its alleged objectives. I have also indicated that the legislation makes no attempt to weigh, assess or balance the seriousness of the conduct which may have resulted in imprison ment and the resultant deprivation of a Charter guar anteed right. Finally, I have indicated that as a neces sary result of the legislation, and not merely of its
imperfect application, its actual operation in any par ticular case will depend on wholly fortuitous circum stances which bear no relationship either to the alleged objectives or to the conduct of the prisoners whose rights are thus taken away. Even assuming the alleged objectives to be valid, paragraph 51(e) simply cannot be characterized as a measured and propor tionate means of achieving them with due regard for the importance of the rights taken away.
To summarize, it is my view that paragraph 51(e) does not have the objectives which are claimed for it. While I do not deny that at least some of those objec tives, notably that of punishing offenders, may be legitimate, neither the text nor the operation of the legislation supports the view that this is in fact what Parliament was aiming at. Even assuming the validity and legitimacy of the ends, the means are irrational, arbitrary and disproportionate. I conclude, as did Strayer J., that paragraph 51(e) impairs the rights granted by section 3 of the Charter and that it is not a reasonable limit thereon such as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society.
I would dismiss the appeal with costs.
PRATTE J.A.: I agree.
DESJARDINS J.A.: I agree.
 You are being directed to the most recent version of the statute which may not be the version considered at the time of the judgment.